Author(s): | Kasper, Sherryl Davis |
---|---|
Reviewer(s): | Garrison, Roger W. |
Published by EH.NET (April 2003)
Sherryl Davis Kasper, The Revival of Laissez-Faire in American Macroeconomic
Theory: A Case Study of the Pioneers. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar, 2002.
viii + 177 pp. ?49.45/$75 (hardcover), ISBN: 1-84064-606-3.
Reviewed for EH.NET by Roger W. Garrison, Department of Economics, Auburn
University.
The title phrase “laissez-faire” is pressed into service as the common
denominator for this close-up look at the “pioneers” who have given shape to
market-oriented macroeconomics in the United States. In a chapter-per-pioneer
format, Kasper presents the ideas of Frank Knight, Henry Simons, Friedrich
Hayek, Milton Friedman, James Buchanan, and Robert Lucas. Each chapter provides
a brief personal history, identifies a “pre-analytic vision,” and presents the
case for laissez-faire. The reader soon realizes that this common rallying cry
of classical liberalism serves only loosely as a common denominator.
Laissez-faire appears variously throughout the book as a presumption, a
principle, a policy recommendation, a standard, an ideal, and a modeling
technique.
Kasper, who takes her own orientation from the institutionalist school, doesn’t
play favorites among the pioneers. As announced in the short introductory
chapter, her primary concern is with the basis for the advocacy of
laissez-faire: (1) Are there strong ideological influences? (2) Does the
theoretical resolution to some contemporary economic problem add to the case
for less rather than more government involvement? (3) Do new tools and methods
help to reveal the merits of unhampered markets?
Kasper’s ultimate verdict is not easily summarized, but the careful reader will
see that it emerges as an evolving pattern of answers to the questions about
the basis for the advocacy of laissez-faire.
A passing reference (p. 149) to the “taint of ideological commitment to
laissez-faire” supposedly associated with the early pioneers hints that the
later pioneers labored under a taint by association. Kasper seems to take for
granted that ideological commitments lie somewhere below the surface of the
arguments actually made — just how far below being the only live issue. She
acknowledges that there were genuine efforts in the 1960s and 1970s to
understand the problems of inflation and stagflation — problems that were
inadequately addressed by the Keynesian orthodoxy. And she makes the judgment
that Friedman’s monetarism and Buchanan’s public choice theory had more appeal
than could be accounted for in terms of the implicit ideology. But while
monetarism and public-choice theory were born of
ideology-cum-resolution-to-contemporary-problem, Lucas’s new classicism was
born of resolution-to-contemporary-problem-cum-new-tools-and-methods. Only in
this most recent reincarnation was market-oriented macroeconomics able to
dominate the field.
But was it the rigor of new classical methods or the adherence to laissez-faire
— or possibly something else — that won professional acceptance? Kasper’s
answer to this question seems to hinge on the nature of the arguments of the
early and the late pioneers. The early pioneers made negative arguments.
Because of unquantifiable uncertainties (Knight), the fragmentation of
knowledge (Hayek), the lack of timely data (Simons and Friedman), and/or the
lack of suitable motivation (Buchanan), we cannot expect policymakers to
engineer results that are superior to those that emerge spontaneously in a
competitive market economy. With such negative arguments, it was difficult to
attract adherents in large numbers. Survival rather than revival was the order
of the day, and to that end the Mont P?lerin Society — suggested by Simons
before his untimely death in 1946 and organized by Hayek in 1947 — became
crucial.
Lucas, by contrast, offered a positive argument. He brought laissez-faire into
play up front as a modeling technique, rather than saving it as a possible
policy recommendation. As a consequence, the macroeconomic modeler of the late
1970s and early 1980s could make full use of the mathematical techniques
already in the economist’s tool box, could learn some new modeling techniques
that were part and parcel with new classicism, and could possibly develop still
more techniques to push the envelope of this new mode of theorizing. Devising
so-called fully articulated artificial economies, calibrating the models on the
basis of actual movements in real-world macroeconomic magnitudes, subjecting
the model economies to hypothetical shocks, and making predictions on this
basis occupied many practitioners. And it was all heady business, despite — or
possibly because of — the tenuous link between theory and reality. Kasper
mentions — but almost as an aside — that during the heyday of new classicism,
the revival may have been driven by the opportunity to employ sophisticated
techniques in the pursuit of professional advancement.
In the final page-and-a-half of the book, Kasper notes that the supremacy of
laissez-faire in new classical dress was short-lived and argues that in any
case Lucas’s contribution was not free of the ideological taint. Beginning in
the early 1980s, his Friedman-friendly version of new classicism gave way to
real business cycle theory, which accorded no significant role to money, and to
new Keynesianism, whose sticky wages and menu costs warned against leaving
matters to the market. Further, an ideological taint attaches to Lucas’s new
classicism, in Kasper’s reckoning, because the tools that Lucas borrowed from
Friedman were themselves influenced by Friedman’s ideological commitment to
laissez-faire. The reader gets the idea that the issue of ideology has special
significance for our understanding of market-oriented macroeconomics. But that
special significance is never put into a more general context. Nowhere in the
book is there a discussion or even a mention of the ideological underpinnings
of Marxism, Keynesianism, or Institutionalism.
Nor does Kasper offer a comparison of new classicism with old classicism. The
old classical economists favored a system of natural liberty partly on grounds
of moral philosophy and partly because of their understanding of the economic
order. Laissez-faire was a presumption, a default-mode policy. It assigned the
burden of proof to anyone (including themselves) who proposed to interfere with
the natural order. Would Kasper see the classical commitment to laissez-faire
as ideologically tainted? Presumably she would, since the arguments offered by
Adam Smith were the same in this respect as those offered almost two centuries
later by Hayek, Friedman, and Buchanan.
Beyond the issues of ideological taint, readers will find interesting material
in Kasper’s book. Her survey of the pioneers demonstrates, for instance, just
how broadly the laissez-faire label is applied. Henry Simons, who is well known
for wanting to use the tax system to redistribute income, also favored a tax on
advertising, the revenues to be used for consumer education and the
establishment of uniform commodity standards (p. 43). Milton Friedman, heavily
influenced by Simons, reread his work in later years and was astounded to
realize that these ideas were was once thought to have a pro-market orientation
(p. 100).
Roger W. Garrison is Professor of Economics at Auburn University. He is author
of Time and Money: The Macroeconomics of Capital Structure (Routledge,
2001).
Subject(s): | Macroeconomics and Fluctuations |
---|---|
Geographic Area(s): | North America |
Time Period(s): | 20th Century: WWII and post-WWII |