Published by EH.NET (May 2001)
Richard Whatmore, Republicanism and the French Revolution: An Intellectual
History of Jean-Baptiste Say’s Political Economy. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2000. xiv + 248 pp.$70 (cloth), ISBN: 0-19-924115-5.
Reviewed for EH.NET by William Baumol, Department of Economics, New York
University.
The central objective of this book is to describe, both in light of the
writings of contemporaries and from internal evidence in Jean-Baptiste Say’s
own writings, the underlying orientation of that author — the political
philosophy by which he was guided. The author, a lecturer at the University of
Sussex, is extraordinarily well informed about the pertinent literature of the
time, and perhaps tells us more about this material than some readers may want
to know. But, on the basis of those writings, he offers us insights into Say’s
predilections and, in particular, his views on political and social issues,
that are likely to have escaped even careful readers of Say’s best-known
writings. In particular, the author emphasizes that Say was not a liberal in
the tradition of the British classical economists, nor a full-fledged follower
of the path of Adam Smith (though he points out in the very first page of
Chapter 1 that Jean-Baptiste’s own son, Horace Say, asserted that, contrary to
Whatmore, such was indeed his father’s orientation). Here, we are told, Say’s
position also did not favor full democracy or even the constitutional royalist
regime of the United Kingdom at the beginning of the nineteenth century.
Instead, Say’s position was consistent and avid “republicanism.”
The term, however, is used in a sense very different from ours. The author
describes eighteenth century “republican political economy” in the following
passage: Republican political economy demanded the establishment and
maintenance of a moderate level of wealth for all citizens. Ranks had to be
abolished to prevent aristocracy or inequality from recurring. The sovereignty
of the [propertied] people was to be coupled with the decentralization of
political and administrative power to the citizens of a locality. Despite
this, the republic was to remain a unified state. Its laws would embody the
public good and its patriotic citizenry would be dedicated to defending and
maintaining the state. The modern republic was a commercial society in the
sense that wealth derived from trade and industry was to be encouraged as an
antidote to the poverty of the state and the citizenry. Commercialization was
to be welcomed as long as it remained compatible with republican morality and
an egalitarian social structure. A republic was therefore not solely to be
created by making laws that prevented domination and abolished monarchy, as
many eighteenth-century British radicals supposed. Far more important was the
creation of a republican political culture based on a blend of commercial with
traditionally conceived virtuous manners. Without cultural transformation any
projected political innovations would be doomed to failure. (p. 31)
Implicit in this passage are the other goals that the author claims to have
been Say’s — severely reduced inequality with moderate wealth for all,
dedication to virtue and good manners on the part of the population, and
education of the public as well as the members of government to the need for
and benefits of such behavior, as well as the requirements of a
well-functioning economy that is a necessary condition for achievement of
these goals.
All of this is entirely plausible, though the author provides us with
remarkably little in Say’s writings, at least after he had attained maturity,
that makes these points explicitly. But Whatmore goes further than this. He
implies that this is what Say’s Trait? and his other writings in
economics are, essentially, all about. Even Say’s law is not to be properly
understood without this information: “In consequence, it ismisleading to group
him [Say] with exponents of classical political economy in Britain, as many
historians of economic thought continue to do. Say’s conception of utility
must be seen as a product of a French discussion about public virtue rather
than a partially-formed building block of a new science. Say’s ‘Law’, by
contrast with the use made of it by British Ricardians, was intended to combat
fears of ‘general gluts’ by the introduction of specific ranks and manners”
(p. 218).
In taking this position, it seems clear to me, the author goes too far.
Rereading of the Trait? surely indicates that the author intended the
book to be a work of political economy in the standard sense, and one
completely divorced from political connotations. Indeed, Say emphasizes this
in the first page of his introduction: “Since the time of Adam Smith, it
appears to me, these two very distinct inquiries have been uniformly
separated, the term political economy being now confined to the science
which treats of wealth, and that of politics, to designate the
relations existing between a government and its people, and the relations of
different states to each other” ( A Treatise of Political Economy,
American translation of the fourth edition of the Trait?, Philadelphia,
1834, pp. xv-xvi).
This is not to deny that Whatmore’s observations are illuminating. They do
help us to understand Say as author, just as Jacob Viner’s emphasis (The
Role of Providence in the Social Order, Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1972, p. 81) of the religious connotation of Adam Smith’s invisible
hand passage (“invisible hand” being a common eighteenth-century reference to
the hand of Providence) helps us to understand what Smith meant in this
passage. But a claim that The Wealth of Nations is therefore to be
interpreted as predominantly a religious tract would surely be misleading. And
it seems to me equally misleading to interpret the Trait? as a manual
of republicanism rather than, primarily, as a work of political economy, as
the title of the book tells us, and as Say tells us the term was
conventionally interpreted at the time.
William J. Baumol, Professor of Economics, New York University. is currently
working on a book investigating the explanation of the superior growth record
of free-market economies and, most recently, is co-author with Ralph Gomory of
Global Trade and Conflicting National Interests, MIT Press, 2001.