Author(s): | Finkelstein, Andrea |
---|---|
Reviewer(s): | Harpham, Edward J. |
Published by EH.NET (June 2002)
Andrea Finkelstein, Harmony and the Balance: An Intellectual History of
Seventeenth-Century English Economic Thought. Ann Arbor: University of
Michigan Press, 2000. x + 381 pp. $49.50 (cloth), ISBN: 0-472-11143-4.
Reviewed for EH.NET by Edward J. Harpham, School of Social Sciences, University
of Texas at Dallas.
Historians of seventeenth-century economic thought in England find themselves
trapped in a rather curious dilemma. On the one hand, most are interested in
understanding the intellectual origins of a modern economic view of the world.
Essentially this means investigating the historical development of the tools of
modern economic analysis. Does a particular writer grasp some aspect of
marginal utility theory or the quantity theory of money? What are the limits to
a particular theorist’s view of economic problems? Following the lead of Joseph
Schumpeter, students adopting this perspective often turn the history of
economic ideas into a history of the tools of economic analysis.
On the other hand, many want to place economic ideas in the seventeenth century
in one of a variety of contexts. One context, for example, involves the
specific historical context out of which specific economic ideas emerge. How
did the economic and political events of the day such as banking or trade
crises shape the economic ideas of a particular writer? What special interests
or biases might influence the development of one set of ideas rather than
another? Here the history of economic thought is turned into one dimension of a
broader sociology of knowledge. Barry Supple’s Commercial Crisis and Change
in England, 1600-1642 (1959) is perhaps the classic example of such an
approach. A second contextual approach tries to grasp economic ideas in terms
of the general intellectual environment of the times. For example, how do the
assumptions of a modern scientific or an individualistic worldview affect the
way economic theorists conceptualize economic problems? Joyce Appleby’s
Economic Thought and Ideology in Seventeenth Century England (1978) is a
notable contribution to this genre. Finally, there is the biographical context.
English economic writers in the seventeenth century came from a variety of
backgrounds, ranging from merchants seeking special privileges to intellectuals
committed to a particular political agenda to officials trying to justify
governmental policy. Moreover, their ideas were expressed in a number of
different genres rather than a consistent scientific literature. Biographic
context aims to help explain why certain economic ideas were developed at
particular points in time, and what their conceptual limitations might be.
Karen Vaughn’s John Locke, Economist and Social Scientist (1980) is an
excellent example of this approach.
The problem facing the historian of economic thought is how to integrate the
study of the tools and concepts of modern economic analysis with one or all of
these contextual approaches. Andrea Finkelstein’s strategy echoes that of
E.A.J. Johnson’s Predecessors of Adam Smith (1937) and William Letwin’s
The Origins of Scientific Economics (1963) in many ways. First, she
identifies a number of key contributors to the century’s economic debates. For
Johnson, these figures were Gerard de Malynes, Edward Misselden, Thomas Mun,
William Petty, and Nehemiah Grew. For Letwin, they were Josiah Child, Nicholas
Barbon, John Collins, William Petty, John Locke, and Dudley North. Finkelstein
splits the difference between the two, looking at Malynes, Misselden and Mun in
Part I, at Petty, Child and Locke in Part II, and at North, Barbon, and
Davenant in part III. She is unapologetic in her selection, noting that these
figures are generally recognized by historians of economic thought as the best
that the century had to offer.
Second, she organizes her study of each trio of theorists around a few themes.
Part I seeks to explain how the balance of trade theory articulated by Malynes,
Misselden and Mun provided a new perspective for viewing the self-interested
behavior and the market alongside a more traditional organic view of society as
a harmonious whole. Many of the tensions and contradictions in their thought
must be understood in terms of the “logical impasse” created by the attempt to
accommodate balance of trade theory into a societal model of a harmonious
universe. Part II’s analysis of Petty, Child, and Locke is held together by the
idea that new mechanical models of society based on the work of Harvey,
Descartes, and Hobbes displaced the old organic model of the body politic
sometime during the middle decades of the seventeenth century. This new
approach which stressed the uniformity of human behavior and the idea that
individuals acted from a pleasure-pain calculus became the philosophical
foundation of economic thought for two new models of economic life: a
circulatory model and a national accounting model. The central theme of part
III is balance. Essentially what Finkelstein appears to mean here is that each
theorist sought to integrate some new notion of balance into the new models of
polity and economy developed by earlier thinkers in the century.
Third, Finkelstein spends considerable time providing a biographical background
to each of the writers. Each substantive chapter begins with an overview of the
writer’s life and career and an analysis of the controversies that shaped his
economic writings. Finally, most chapters conclude with an in-depth discussion
of the key economic ideas that are found in a particular writer’s work, such as
money, demand, value, circulation and the like.
There is much to be learned from Finkelstein’s book. It is hard to argue with
her choice of figures. All but one is commonly recognized as a leading
contributor to economic thought in the century. The choice of Davenant may
surprise some, being a figure largely ignored in standard histories of modern
economic thought. His contributions to the economic and political controversies
of the day are undeniable and his inclusion may help to broaden most
economists’ understanding of early founders of their discipline.The
biographical analysis of these figures is excellent, moving beyond that of
predecessors like Johnson and Letwin. Finkelstein takes seriously the idea that
we must understand the context in which the author is writing if we are to
grasp the ideas developed by an author. Similarly her analysis of various
modern analytical ideas developed by each of the theorists is thoughtful and
creative, while not being overly critical. Finkelstein is sensitive to the idea
that these writers might have something to teach modern economists about the
way we have come to think about economic issues and problems.
The problem with the book resides in the larger themes that Finkelstein tries
to use to make the book a unified whole. Some of these themes work well. For
example, the idea that the balance of trade theory of Malynes, Misselden and
Mun may have introduced an irreconcilable tension into an organic view of the
body politic is intriguing. Finkelstein does a pretty good job arguing her case
in Part I. But the unifying themes of mechanism and balance in Part II and III
are less well developed and need a more careful elaboration. There is no doubt
that the mechanistic universe of Harvey, Descartes, and Hobbes played a major
role in shaping the intellectual climate of seventeenth-century England. But
Finkelstein’s contention that it may be a unifying feature tying together the
economic thought of Petty, Child, and Locke is suggestive at best. Her rich
discussion of each thinker’s work seems to belie the fact that they are taken
from a common cloth. Similar problems haunt the analysis of the idea of balance
in Part III. Davenant’s civic humanist concerns over balance in a commercial
society seem to be a far cry from the concerns of North or Barbon. Throughout
Part III, it is often difficult to understand what is being balanced or what is
balancing what. As in Part II, some of the grand themes of the book tend to get
in the way of the rather intriguing discussions of each individual thinker
Other problems exist with Finkelstein’s attempt to place an individual’s
economic ideas into larger intellectual contexts like Baconian
authoritarianism, millenarianism, civic humanism, natural law theory, or
theories of Aristotelian harmony. While readily using these terms to situate
the economic ideas of seventeenth-century England, Finkelstein does not always
carefully explain the complexity and mixed meanings built into these concepts.
Nor does she ever adequately explain why some authors appealed to one set of
ideas while others appealed to another. Was an economic way of thinking about
the world trapped in a variety of competing perspectives or was it integrally
connected to them?
One shouldn’t be too critical of Finkelstein’s effort to bring some order to a
myriad of economic arguments developed by thinkers in the seventeenth century.
Finkelstein’s study reminds us how complex intellectual discourse was in the
early modern era and why we should be wary of one-size-fits-all
interpretations. Faults aside, Finkelstein has presented us with an insightful
and, at times, thought-provoking book on economic ideas in seventeenth-century
England. It is a good starting point for anyone interested in gaining a deeper
insight into the controversies and ideas that shaped early modern economic
thinking.
Edward J. Harpham has published numerous articles in the history of
seventeenth- and eighteenth-century political and economic thought. He is the
editor of John Locke’s Two Treatises of Government: New Interpretations
(1992).
Subject(s): | History of Economic Thought; Methodology |
---|---|
Geographic Area(s): | Europe |
Time Period(s): | 17th Century |